When to use Iterated Forcing The Next CEO of Stack OverflowIs the axiom of universes 'harmless'?Do we usually assume the consistency of ZFC when we use forcing?Dependent choice does not imply “the reals are well-ordered”; citation?Existence of Certain Names in Iterated ForcingBest Less-Famous Texts for ForcingA question about $aleph_1$-dense sets and the basis problem for uncountable linear orderingsExercise of Iterated Forcing from Kunen's bookProvability of 'generalized continuum hypothesis implies axiom of choice' over ZFRudimentary results in iterated forcing.Standard fact about iterated forcing

Why don't programming languages automatically manage the synchronous/asynchronous problem?

What flight has the highest ratio of time difference to flight time?

Is there a way to save my career from absolute disaster?

Several mode to write the symbol of a vector

What happens if you roll doubles 3 times then land on "Go to jail?"

I believe this to be a fraud - hired, then asked to cash check and send cash as Bitcoin

Received an invoice from my ex-employer billing me for training; how to handle?

What's the best way to handle refactoring a big file?

Is it possible to search for a directory/file combination?

Unreliable Magic - Is it worth it?

Would a completely good Muggle be able to use a wand?

If/When UK leaves the EU, can a future goverment conduct a referendum to join the EU?

Bold, vivid family

Can we say or write : "No, it'sn't"?

Written every which way

Is there a difference between "Fahrstuhl" and "Aufzug"

What exact does MIB represent in SNMP? How is it different from OID?

Make solar eclipses exceedingly rare, but still have new moons

How do I transpose the 1st and -1th levels of an arbitrarily nested array?

What can we do to stop prior company from asking us questions?

Preparing Indesign booklet with .psd graphics for print

Sending manuscript to multiple publishers

How do I make a variable always equal to the result of some calculations?

Are there any unintended negative consequences to allowing PCs to gain multiple levels at once in a short milestone-XP game?



When to use Iterated Forcing



The Next CEO of Stack OverflowIs the axiom of universes 'harmless'?Do we usually assume the consistency of ZFC when we use forcing?Dependent choice does not imply “the reals are well-ordered”; citation?Existence of Certain Names in Iterated ForcingBest Less-Famous Texts for ForcingA question about $aleph_1$-dense sets and the basis problem for uncountable linear orderingsExercise of Iterated Forcing from Kunen's bookProvability of 'generalized continuum hypothesis implies axiom of choice' over ZFRudimentary results in iterated forcing.Standard fact about iterated forcing










4












$begingroup$


Iterated forcing is useful for separating cardinal characteristics, and to prove the consistency of Martin's axiom. My question is, what is it about these problems determine that a normal forcing proof can't work and that we require multiple forcings?



What about a consistency result determines that it need be proved through iterated forcing rather than ordinary forcing?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    Always. All forcing is iterated forcing.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 days ago















4












$begingroup$


Iterated forcing is useful for separating cardinal characteristics, and to prove the consistency of Martin's axiom. My question is, what is it about these problems determine that a normal forcing proof can't work and that we require multiple forcings?



What about a consistency result determines that it need be proved through iterated forcing rather than ordinary forcing?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    Always. All forcing is iterated forcing.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 days ago













4












4








4





$begingroup$


Iterated forcing is useful for separating cardinal characteristics, and to prove the consistency of Martin's axiom. My question is, what is it about these problems determine that a normal forcing proof can't work and that we require multiple forcings?



What about a consistency result determines that it need be proved through iterated forcing rather than ordinary forcing?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




Iterated forcing is useful for separating cardinal characteristics, and to prove the consistency of Martin's axiom. My question is, what is it about these problems determine that a normal forcing proof can't work and that we require multiple forcings?



What about a consistency result determines that it need be proved through iterated forcing rather than ordinary forcing?







set-theory forcing






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked 2 days ago









MarmosetMarmoset

406




406











  • $begingroup$
    Always. All forcing is iterated forcing.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 days ago
















  • $begingroup$
    Always. All forcing is iterated forcing.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 days ago















$begingroup$
Always. All forcing is iterated forcing.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
2 days ago




$begingroup$
Always. All forcing is iterated forcing.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
2 days ago










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















5












$begingroup$

There's no criteria that requires to be satisfied in order to use iterated forcing. Not only that, but since iterating forcing is the same as taking a single forcing extension (using the iteration poset), the question sort of falls flat on itself.



Even worse, with the exception of a certain class of "minimal" generic extension, most (in some sense) forcing notions are in fact an iteration, since they can be decomposed to iteration of one or more subforcings. For example, adding a Cohen real can be thought of as adding two Cohen reals one after the other. And collapsing $omega_1$ can be thought as first adding a Cohen real, then adding a branch to the Suslin tree added by that Cohen real, and then collapsing $omega_1$.




So why do we even use iterated forcing?



Because it's convenient. Because it is easier to break down a large problem into smaller problems, and then deal with them, one at a time. When forcing Martin's Axiom, for example, it is easier to deal with the forcing notions one step at a time, rather than trying to somehow capture all of the existing ones, and the ones who would come, simultaneously.



Even worse. The iterative approach to Martin's Axiom is pure magic. Every limit step adds Cohen reals. Every Cohen real adds a Suslin tree. Martin's Axiom implies that there are no Suslin trees.



How does it happen? Well. Because of the very nature of the iteration, at each step we anticipate "a problem", and we solve it.



Other times we might want to construct an object via forcing, but our starting model would require to have certain objects which are not guaranteed to exist. Or perhaps the construction would require a certain degree of genericity over the model, so first adding something new to work with is a good thing. In those approaches we start with $V$, we extend it once with a preparation (which itself may or may not be an iteration, e.g. Martin's Axiom or indestructibility of large cardinals), and then perform one or two extensions to obtain a final model.



Yes, we can describe the whole thing as a single forcing poset. But why? It will offer no better result, and will only increase the difficulty when trying to describe your objects or reason as to why they have this or that property.



For this reason exactly it is sometimes convenient to think about a Cohen real as a subset of $omega$, sometimes as a binary sequence in $2^omega$, and sometimes as a general sequence in $omega^omega$. But sometimes it's easier to think about a single Cohen real as infinitely many different Cohen reals instead, exactly for that reason.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    This is a great answer, I had never thought about the fact that adding a Cohen real is essentially iterated forcing in itself. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Marmoset
    2 days ago


















4












$begingroup$

Maybe I can add a natural example to Asaf's great answer. In the case of establishing Borel's conjecture, iterated forcing naturally comes up in the construction. Borel's conjecture states that all strong measure zero sets of reals are countable (it is not important what that means). As it turns out, this statement is independent of ZFC. It is not too hard to construct a counterexample to it using CH. To show that BC is consistent, you need forcing. But how do you force BC? Richard Laver found a poset (now called Laver forcing) that is easy to describe and has the following property:
If $V[g]$ is a generic extension of $V$ via Laver forcing and $Ain V$ is a set of reals which is strong measure zero in $V[g]$, then $A$ is countable (both in $V$ and $V[g]$). (Note that the evaluation of the statement "$A$ is strong measure zero" may change from $V$ to $V[g]$). Now you have made some progress, there are no "old" counterexamples to BC anymore. But there still might be new counterexamples! It is now clear that one should try to iterate this process to make the new counterexamples vanish in the limit. This turns out to work, however it is not enough to iterate this just $omega$ or $omega_1$-many times, it is important to do it $omega_2$-many times (otherwise CH might still hold in the extension). Moreover one has to choose the support correctly, in this case it is countable support for technical reasons.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I think this is a bit problematic as written. I assume you are using the term "ordinary forcing" in a purely informal fashion, but it is really to informal to be useful. Why would adding $aleph_mathfrak c^+$ Cohen reals not be considered ordinary?
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    In fact, it reads as if you are claiming that there is a well understood and reasonably wide and varied class of "ordinary forcing notions", and that no forcing in this class can force $lnotmathsfCH$ and (perhaps) that no forcing in this class is forcing isomorphic to an iteration.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    I agree that this is problematic. "Ordinary forcing" is the term OP used to phrase their question and I simply tried to make sense of this to appeal to OPs intuition.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I have edited out this section to avoid further confusion.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3164683%2fwhen-to-use-iterated-forcing%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes








2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









5












$begingroup$

There's no criteria that requires to be satisfied in order to use iterated forcing. Not only that, but since iterating forcing is the same as taking a single forcing extension (using the iteration poset), the question sort of falls flat on itself.



Even worse, with the exception of a certain class of "minimal" generic extension, most (in some sense) forcing notions are in fact an iteration, since they can be decomposed to iteration of one or more subforcings. For example, adding a Cohen real can be thought of as adding two Cohen reals one after the other. And collapsing $omega_1$ can be thought as first adding a Cohen real, then adding a branch to the Suslin tree added by that Cohen real, and then collapsing $omega_1$.




So why do we even use iterated forcing?



Because it's convenient. Because it is easier to break down a large problem into smaller problems, and then deal with them, one at a time. When forcing Martin's Axiom, for example, it is easier to deal with the forcing notions one step at a time, rather than trying to somehow capture all of the existing ones, and the ones who would come, simultaneously.



Even worse. The iterative approach to Martin's Axiom is pure magic. Every limit step adds Cohen reals. Every Cohen real adds a Suslin tree. Martin's Axiom implies that there are no Suslin trees.



How does it happen? Well. Because of the very nature of the iteration, at each step we anticipate "a problem", and we solve it.



Other times we might want to construct an object via forcing, but our starting model would require to have certain objects which are not guaranteed to exist. Or perhaps the construction would require a certain degree of genericity over the model, so first adding something new to work with is a good thing. In those approaches we start with $V$, we extend it once with a preparation (which itself may or may not be an iteration, e.g. Martin's Axiom or indestructibility of large cardinals), and then perform one or two extensions to obtain a final model.



Yes, we can describe the whole thing as a single forcing poset. But why? It will offer no better result, and will only increase the difficulty when trying to describe your objects or reason as to why they have this or that property.



For this reason exactly it is sometimes convenient to think about a Cohen real as a subset of $omega$, sometimes as a binary sequence in $2^omega$, and sometimes as a general sequence in $omega^omega$. But sometimes it's easier to think about a single Cohen real as infinitely many different Cohen reals instead, exactly for that reason.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    This is a great answer, I had never thought about the fact that adding a Cohen real is essentially iterated forcing in itself. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Marmoset
    2 days ago















5












$begingroup$

There's no criteria that requires to be satisfied in order to use iterated forcing. Not only that, but since iterating forcing is the same as taking a single forcing extension (using the iteration poset), the question sort of falls flat on itself.



Even worse, with the exception of a certain class of "minimal" generic extension, most (in some sense) forcing notions are in fact an iteration, since they can be decomposed to iteration of one or more subforcings. For example, adding a Cohen real can be thought of as adding two Cohen reals one after the other. And collapsing $omega_1$ can be thought as first adding a Cohen real, then adding a branch to the Suslin tree added by that Cohen real, and then collapsing $omega_1$.




So why do we even use iterated forcing?



Because it's convenient. Because it is easier to break down a large problem into smaller problems, and then deal with them, one at a time. When forcing Martin's Axiom, for example, it is easier to deal with the forcing notions one step at a time, rather than trying to somehow capture all of the existing ones, and the ones who would come, simultaneously.



Even worse. The iterative approach to Martin's Axiom is pure magic. Every limit step adds Cohen reals. Every Cohen real adds a Suslin tree. Martin's Axiom implies that there are no Suslin trees.



How does it happen? Well. Because of the very nature of the iteration, at each step we anticipate "a problem", and we solve it.



Other times we might want to construct an object via forcing, but our starting model would require to have certain objects which are not guaranteed to exist. Or perhaps the construction would require a certain degree of genericity over the model, so first adding something new to work with is a good thing. In those approaches we start with $V$, we extend it once with a preparation (which itself may or may not be an iteration, e.g. Martin's Axiom or indestructibility of large cardinals), and then perform one or two extensions to obtain a final model.



Yes, we can describe the whole thing as a single forcing poset. But why? It will offer no better result, and will only increase the difficulty when trying to describe your objects or reason as to why they have this or that property.



For this reason exactly it is sometimes convenient to think about a Cohen real as a subset of $omega$, sometimes as a binary sequence in $2^omega$, and sometimes as a general sequence in $omega^omega$. But sometimes it's easier to think about a single Cohen real as infinitely many different Cohen reals instead, exactly for that reason.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    This is a great answer, I had never thought about the fact that adding a Cohen real is essentially iterated forcing in itself. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Marmoset
    2 days ago













5












5








5





$begingroup$

There's no criteria that requires to be satisfied in order to use iterated forcing. Not only that, but since iterating forcing is the same as taking a single forcing extension (using the iteration poset), the question sort of falls flat on itself.



Even worse, with the exception of a certain class of "minimal" generic extension, most (in some sense) forcing notions are in fact an iteration, since they can be decomposed to iteration of one or more subforcings. For example, adding a Cohen real can be thought of as adding two Cohen reals one after the other. And collapsing $omega_1$ can be thought as first adding a Cohen real, then adding a branch to the Suslin tree added by that Cohen real, and then collapsing $omega_1$.




So why do we even use iterated forcing?



Because it's convenient. Because it is easier to break down a large problem into smaller problems, and then deal with them, one at a time. When forcing Martin's Axiom, for example, it is easier to deal with the forcing notions one step at a time, rather than trying to somehow capture all of the existing ones, and the ones who would come, simultaneously.



Even worse. The iterative approach to Martin's Axiom is pure magic. Every limit step adds Cohen reals. Every Cohen real adds a Suslin tree. Martin's Axiom implies that there are no Suslin trees.



How does it happen? Well. Because of the very nature of the iteration, at each step we anticipate "a problem", and we solve it.



Other times we might want to construct an object via forcing, but our starting model would require to have certain objects which are not guaranteed to exist. Or perhaps the construction would require a certain degree of genericity over the model, so first adding something new to work with is a good thing. In those approaches we start with $V$, we extend it once with a preparation (which itself may or may not be an iteration, e.g. Martin's Axiom or indestructibility of large cardinals), and then perform one or two extensions to obtain a final model.



Yes, we can describe the whole thing as a single forcing poset. But why? It will offer no better result, and will only increase the difficulty when trying to describe your objects or reason as to why they have this or that property.



For this reason exactly it is sometimes convenient to think about a Cohen real as a subset of $omega$, sometimes as a binary sequence in $2^omega$, and sometimes as a general sequence in $omega^omega$. But sometimes it's easier to think about a single Cohen real as infinitely many different Cohen reals instead, exactly for that reason.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



There's no criteria that requires to be satisfied in order to use iterated forcing. Not only that, but since iterating forcing is the same as taking a single forcing extension (using the iteration poset), the question sort of falls flat on itself.



Even worse, with the exception of a certain class of "minimal" generic extension, most (in some sense) forcing notions are in fact an iteration, since they can be decomposed to iteration of one or more subforcings. For example, adding a Cohen real can be thought of as adding two Cohen reals one after the other. And collapsing $omega_1$ can be thought as first adding a Cohen real, then adding a branch to the Suslin tree added by that Cohen real, and then collapsing $omega_1$.




So why do we even use iterated forcing?



Because it's convenient. Because it is easier to break down a large problem into smaller problems, and then deal with them, one at a time. When forcing Martin's Axiom, for example, it is easier to deal with the forcing notions one step at a time, rather than trying to somehow capture all of the existing ones, and the ones who would come, simultaneously.



Even worse. The iterative approach to Martin's Axiom is pure magic. Every limit step adds Cohen reals. Every Cohen real adds a Suslin tree. Martin's Axiom implies that there are no Suslin trees.



How does it happen? Well. Because of the very nature of the iteration, at each step we anticipate "a problem", and we solve it.



Other times we might want to construct an object via forcing, but our starting model would require to have certain objects which are not guaranteed to exist. Or perhaps the construction would require a certain degree of genericity over the model, so first adding something new to work with is a good thing. In those approaches we start with $V$, we extend it once with a preparation (which itself may or may not be an iteration, e.g. Martin's Axiom or indestructibility of large cardinals), and then perform one or two extensions to obtain a final model.



Yes, we can describe the whole thing as a single forcing poset. But why? It will offer no better result, and will only increase the difficulty when trying to describe your objects or reason as to why they have this or that property.



For this reason exactly it is sometimes convenient to think about a Cohen real as a subset of $omega$, sometimes as a binary sequence in $2^omega$, and sometimes as a general sequence in $omega^omega$. But sometimes it's easier to think about a single Cohen real as infinitely many different Cohen reals instead, exactly for that reason.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered 2 days ago









Asaf KaragilaAsaf Karagila

307k33439771




307k33439771











  • $begingroup$
    This is a great answer, I had never thought about the fact that adding a Cohen real is essentially iterated forcing in itself. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Marmoset
    2 days ago
















  • $begingroup$
    This is a great answer, I had never thought about the fact that adding a Cohen real is essentially iterated forcing in itself. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Marmoset
    2 days ago















$begingroup$
This is a great answer, I had never thought about the fact that adding a Cohen real is essentially iterated forcing in itself. Thanks!
$endgroup$
– Marmoset
2 days ago




$begingroup$
This is a great answer, I had never thought about the fact that adding a Cohen real is essentially iterated forcing in itself. Thanks!
$endgroup$
– Marmoset
2 days ago











4












$begingroup$

Maybe I can add a natural example to Asaf's great answer. In the case of establishing Borel's conjecture, iterated forcing naturally comes up in the construction. Borel's conjecture states that all strong measure zero sets of reals are countable (it is not important what that means). As it turns out, this statement is independent of ZFC. It is not too hard to construct a counterexample to it using CH. To show that BC is consistent, you need forcing. But how do you force BC? Richard Laver found a poset (now called Laver forcing) that is easy to describe and has the following property:
If $V[g]$ is a generic extension of $V$ via Laver forcing and $Ain V$ is a set of reals which is strong measure zero in $V[g]$, then $A$ is countable (both in $V$ and $V[g]$). (Note that the evaluation of the statement "$A$ is strong measure zero" may change from $V$ to $V[g]$). Now you have made some progress, there are no "old" counterexamples to BC anymore. But there still might be new counterexamples! It is now clear that one should try to iterate this process to make the new counterexamples vanish in the limit. This turns out to work, however it is not enough to iterate this just $omega$ or $omega_1$-many times, it is important to do it $omega_2$-many times (otherwise CH might still hold in the extension). Moreover one has to choose the support correctly, in this case it is countable support for technical reasons.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I think this is a bit problematic as written. I assume you are using the term "ordinary forcing" in a purely informal fashion, but it is really to informal to be useful. Why would adding $aleph_mathfrak c^+$ Cohen reals not be considered ordinary?
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    In fact, it reads as if you are claiming that there is a well understood and reasonably wide and varied class of "ordinary forcing notions", and that no forcing in this class can force $lnotmathsfCH$ and (perhaps) that no forcing in this class is forcing isomorphic to an iteration.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    I agree that this is problematic. "Ordinary forcing" is the term OP used to phrase their question and I simply tried to make sense of this to appeal to OPs intuition.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I have edited out this section to avoid further confusion.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago















4












$begingroup$

Maybe I can add a natural example to Asaf's great answer. In the case of establishing Borel's conjecture, iterated forcing naturally comes up in the construction. Borel's conjecture states that all strong measure zero sets of reals are countable (it is not important what that means). As it turns out, this statement is independent of ZFC. It is not too hard to construct a counterexample to it using CH. To show that BC is consistent, you need forcing. But how do you force BC? Richard Laver found a poset (now called Laver forcing) that is easy to describe and has the following property:
If $V[g]$ is a generic extension of $V$ via Laver forcing and $Ain V$ is a set of reals which is strong measure zero in $V[g]$, then $A$ is countable (both in $V$ and $V[g]$). (Note that the evaluation of the statement "$A$ is strong measure zero" may change from $V$ to $V[g]$). Now you have made some progress, there are no "old" counterexamples to BC anymore. But there still might be new counterexamples! It is now clear that one should try to iterate this process to make the new counterexamples vanish in the limit. This turns out to work, however it is not enough to iterate this just $omega$ or $omega_1$-many times, it is important to do it $omega_2$-many times (otherwise CH might still hold in the extension). Moreover one has to choose the support correctly, in this case it is countable support for technical reasons.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I think this is a bit problematic as written. I assume you are using the term "ordinary forcing" in a purely informal fashion, but it is really to informal to be useful. Why would adding $aleph_mathfrak c^+$ Cohen reals not be considered ordinary?
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    In fact, it reads as if you are claiming that there is a well understood and reasonably wide and varied class of "ordinary forcing notions", and that no forcing in this class can force $lnotmathsfCH$ and (perhaps) that no forcing in this class is forcing isomorphic to an iteration.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    I agree that this is problematic. "Ordinary forcing" is the term OP used to phrase their question and I simply tried to make sense of this to appeal to OPs intuition.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I have edited out this section to avoid further confusion.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago













4












4








4





$begingroup$

Maybe I can add a natural example to Asaf's great answer. In the case of establishing Borel's conjecture, iterated forcing naturally comes up in the construction. Borel's conjecture states that all strong measure zero sets of reals are countable (it is not important what that means). As it turns out, this statement is independent of ZFC. It is not too hard to construct a counterexample to it using CH. To show that BC is consistent, you need forcing. But how do you force BC? Richard Laver found a poset (now called Laver forcing) that is easy to describe and has the following property:
If $V[g]$ is a generic extension of $V$ via Laver forcing and $Ain V$ is a set of reals which is strong measure zero in $V[g]$, then $A$ is countable (both in $V$ and $V[g]$). (Note that the evaluation of the statement "$A$ is strong measure zero" may change from $V$ to $V[g]$). Now you have made some progress, there are no "old" counterexamples to BC anymore. But there still might be new counterexamples! It is now clear that one should try to iterate this process to make the new counterexamples vanish in the limit. This turns out to work, however it is not enough to iterate this just $omega$ or $omega_1$-many times, it is important to do it $omega_2$-many times (otherwise CH might still hold in the extension). Moreover one has to choose the support correctly, in this case it is countable support for technical reasons.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$



Maybe I can add a natural example to Asaf's great answer. In the case of establishing Borel's conjecture, iterated forcing naturally comes up in the construction. Borel's conjecture states that all strong measure zero sets of reals are countable (it is not important what that means). As it turns out, this statement is independent of ZFC. It is not too hard to construct a counterexample to it using CH. To show that BC is consistent, you need forcing. But how do you force BC? Richard Laver found a poset (now called Laver forcing) that is easy to describe and has the following property:
If $V[g]$ is a generic extension of $V$ via Laver forcing and $Ain V$ is a set of reals which is strong measure zero in $V[g]$, then $A$ is countable (both in $V$ and $V[g]$). (Note that the evaluation of the statement "$A$ is strong measure zero" may change from $V$ to $V[g]$). Now you have made some progress, there are no "old" counterexamples to BC anymore. But there still might be new counterexamples! It is now clear that one should try to iterate this process to make the new counterexamples vanish in the limit. This turns out to work, however it is not enough to iterate this just $omega$ or $omega_1$-many times, it is important to do it $omega_2$-many times (otherwise CH might still hold in the extension). Moreover one has to choose the support correctly, in this case it is countable support for technical reasons.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited 2 days ago

























answered 2 days ago









Andreas LietzAndreas Lietz

39817




39817







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I think this is a bit problematic as written. I assume you are using the term "ordinary forcing" in a purely informal fashion, but it is really to informal to be useful. Why would adding $aleph_mathfrak c^+$ Cohen reals not be considered ordinary?
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    In fact, it reads as if you are claiming that there is a well understood and reasonably wide and varied class of "ordinary forcing notions", and that no forcing in this class can force $lnotmathsfCH$ and (perhaps) that no forcing in this class is forcing isomorphic to an iteration.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    I agree that this is problematic. "Ordinary forcing" is the term OP used to phrase their question and I simply tried to make sense of this to appeal to OPs intuition.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I have edited out this section to avoid further confusion.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago












  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I think this is a bit problematic as written. I assume you are using the term "ordinary forcing" in a purely informal fashion, but it is really to informal to be useful. Why would adding $aleph_mathfrak c^+$ Cohen reals not be considered ordinary?
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    In fact, it reads as if you are claiming that there is a well understood and reasonably wide and varied class of "ordinary forcing notions", and that no forcing in this class can force $lnotmathsfCH$ and (perhaps) that no forcing in this class is forcing isomorphic to an iteration.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    I agree that this is problematic. "Ordinary forcing" is the term OP used to phrase their question and I simply tried to make sense of this to appeal to OPs intuition.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I have edited out this section to avoid further confusion.
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Lietz
    2 days ago







1




1




$begingroup$
I think this is a bit problematic as written. I assume you are using the term "ordinary forcing" in a purely informal fashion, but it is really to informal to be useful. Why would adding $aleph_mathfrak c^+$ Cohen reals not be considered ordinary?
$endgroup$
– Andrés E. Caicedo
2 days ago




$begingroup$
I think this is a bit problematic as written. I assume you are using the term "ordinary forcing" in a purely informal fashion, but it is really to informal to be useful. Why would adding $aleph_mathfrak c^+$ Cohen reals not be considered ordinary?
$endgroup$
– Andrés E. Caicedo
2 days ago












$begingroup$
In fact, it reads as if you are claiming that there is a well understood and reasonably wide and varied class of "ordinary forcing notions", and that no forcing in this class can force $lnotmathsfCH$ and (perhaps) that no forcing in this class is forcing isomorphic to an iteration.
$endgroup$
– Andrés E. Caicedo
2 days ago




$begingroup$
In fact, it reads as if you are claiming that there is a well understood and reasonably wide and varied class of "ordinary forcing notions", and that no forcing in this class can force $lnotmathsfCH$ and (perhaps) that no forcing in this class is forcing isomorphic to an iteration.
$endgroup$
– Andrés E. Caicedo
2 days ago












$begingroup$
I agree that this is problematic. "Ordinary forcing" is the term OP used to phrase their question and I simply tried to make sense of this to appeal to OPs intuition.
$endgroup$
– Andreas Lietz
2 days ago




$begingroup$
I agree that this is problematic. "Ordinary forcing" is the term OP used to phrase their question and I simply tried to make sense of this to appeal to OPs intuition.
$endgroup$
– Andreas Lietz
2 days ago




1




1




$begingroup$
I have edited out this section to avoid further confusion.
$endgroup$
– Andreas Lietz
2 days ago




$begingroup$
I have edited out this section to avoid further confusion.
$endgroup$
– Andreas Lietz
2 days ago

















draft saved

draft discarded
















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid


  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3164683%2fwhen-to-use-iterated-forcing%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Triangular numbers and gcdProving sum of a set is $0 pmod n$ if $n$ is odd, or $fracn2 pmod n$ if $n$ is even?Is greatest common divisor of two numbers really their smallest linear combination?GCD, LCM RelationshipProve a set of nonnegative integers with greatest common divisor 1 and closed under addition has all but finite many nonnegative integers.all pairs of a and b in an equation containing gcdTriangular Numbers Modulo $k$ - Hit All Values?Understanding the Existence and Uniqueness of the GCDGCD and LCM with logical symbolsThe greatest common divisor of two positive integers less than 100 is equal to 3. Their least common multiple is twelve times one of the integers.Suppose that for all integers $x$, $x|a$ and $x|b$ if and only if $x|c$. Then $c = gcd(a,b)$Which is the gcd of 2 numbers which are multiplied and the result is 600000?

Ingelân Ynhâld Etymology | Geografy | Skiednis | Polityk en bestjoer | Ekonomy | Demografy | Kultuer | Klimaat | Sjoch ek | Keppelings om utens | Boarnen, noaten en referinsjes Navigaasjemenuwww.gov.ukOffisjele webside fan it regear fan it Feriene KeninkrykOffisjele webside fan it Britske FerkearsburoNederlânsktalige ynformaasje fan it Britske FerkearsburoOffisjele webside fan English Heritage, de organisaasje dy't him ynset foar it behâld fan it Ingelske kultuergoedYnwennertallen fan alle Britske stêden út 'e folkstelling fan 2011Notes en References, op dizze sideEngland

Boston (Lincolnshire) Stedsbyld | Berne yn Boston | NavigaasjemenuBoston Borough CouncilBoston, Lincolnshire